Zeno's Paradoxes - Part 2
By Francis Moorcroft
This article was originally published in Issue 6 of
The Philosophers' Magazine.
Last time we looked at the first two Paradoxes of Zeno, that attempted to show that
if space is continuous and infinitely divisible then motion is impossible. This
time we will consider the other two Paradoxes that attempt to show that motion is
impossible if space is discrete.
What would it mean to say that space is discrete? It certainly doesn’t
look
as if things move in jerky little jumps. An analogy could be made with motion picture
film: each separate frame is a still photograph, but when it is shown at a rate
of 24 frames per second it looks as if the motion is continuous. So perhaps space
could be like this, with only a finite number of states possible. Zeno’s Paradoxes
are intended to show that this possibility also leads to contradictions, so that
if we accept the conclusion of the first two Paradoxes - that motion is impossible
if space is continuous - then Zeno will have established that motion is impossible
whatever space is like.
The third Paradox is the Arrow. Consider the path of an arrow in flight:
at each instant of its path the arrow occupies some position in space - this is
what it means to say that space is discrete. But to occupy some position in space
is to be at rest. So throughout the entire path of the arrow through space
it is in fact at rest!
The fourth Paradox, the Moving Blocks, is the hardest to follow. Here we
have three rows of blocks of uniform size and an equal distance apart. One row is
at rest, the second row moves past the first row in one direction, the third row
moves past the second row in the opposite direction. Both rows move at the same
speed. We need only consider three blocks in each row and what must happen in the
change from Position 1 to Position 2 in the following diagram:
Position 1
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
A1
|
A2
|
A3
|
|
|
<<<
|
B1
|
B2
|
B3
|
C1
|
C2
|
C3
|
>>>
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Position 2
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
A1
|
A2
|
A3
|
|
|
B1
|
B2
|
B3
|
|
|
C1
|
C2
|
C3
|
|
For this change to happen, B1 and B2 and C3 and C2 each have to pass one member
of the stationary row. But in the same time B1 and B2 will have passed two members
of the C row and C3 and C2 will have passed two members of the B row. As the motion
is uniform, it takes the Bs and Cs an equal amount of time to pass a given object.
But the problem is that they pass two objects in the time it takes to pass only
one.
This argument seems the least impressive of the four as it treats the Bs and Cs
as if they are in motion when they pass each other but at rest when they are themselves
being passed. However, the problem is deeper than this. Consider what would happen
if the members of each row were as near to each other as they could possibly be,
i.e., they occupy adjacent points in space, and that the change from position 1
to position 2 takes place in the smallest amount of time - an instant. Neither of
these assumptions seem problematic. Now in the first instant C3 is opposite B1 and
the next instant it is opposite B3. When did it get to pass B2? There is no time
when this could have happened!
So time, it seems cannot come in instants and space cannot be discrete. We are left
with the option that time and space must be continuous - but that was the assumption
that was criticized by the first two Paradoxes. In fact the Arrow is deeper than
it first appears as the flight of the arrow would be equally impossible even if
space and time were continuous as the arrow would, in effect, have to be at rest
an infinite amount of times during its flight. Thus, whether space is continuous
or whether it is discrete, motion is impossible.