Is It Because He's Fat?
Note: It appears you have not yet completed our interactive activity,
Should You Kill the Fat Man?. If you work through this - it'll take about 5 minutes - before reading the analysis below, things will make a lot more sense. At the end of the activity, you'll find a link that will return you to this page.
A Piece of Bigotry
Three years ago, just before Should You Kill the Fat Man? went live,
we mentioned its existence on a professional philosophy mailing list in the hope
of getting some useful feedback, etc. In among the responses was this little missive:
I have to say that I find this experiment offensive, and always have. There is absolutely
no reason in the logic of the experiment that the person sacrificed should be a
"fat man" or "a (very) fat man." There is a clear subtext that killing a fat man
is somehow different from killing a man.
I am glad to see that some versions of the experiment have recently removed this
piece of bigotry — I just recently saw one in which simply "a person" was suggested
to be sacrificed. But the perpetuation of this gruesome story in its obviously bigoted
anti-fat form is regrettable. The fact that Prof Foot may have invented it in that
form is hardly an excuse.
There are a number of things to say about this. First, it can't simply be "a person",
because that immediately raises the possibility of self-sacrifice (i.e., why not
throw yourself off the bridge rather than push somebody else off?). Second, Judith
Jarvis Thomson, not Philippa Foot, originated the fat man variation of the trolley
problem. Third, there is no clear subtext that killing a fat man is
somehow different from killing a man (not least, it's relevant here that the fat
man variation is intended to provoke the intuition that throwing him off the bridge
is not morally permissible).
The Evidence
Having said all that, the fatness of the fat man is a possible confounding variable:
in other words, if somebody is "anti-fat", then this might be a factor in how they
respond to the fat man scenario(s). So what does the evidence show?
Although we're not able to say with any degree of certainty - because Should You
Kill the Fat Man? was not designed to shed light on this issue - there are a
couple of pieces of data that suggest that if the fatness of the fat man is a confounding
variable, it doesn't have a very big effect.
The first is the fact that people's responses to the fat man scenario tend to be
consistent with the way they answered the earlier questions about their
metaethical views. For example, the first chart to the right should show that
utilitarians are much more likely to throw the fat man off the bridge than
non-utilitarians, presumably because they think that this is what is required by
their utilitarian beliefs (and not because they hate fat people).
The second, and perhaps more significant, piece of data concerns those people
who say it would be wrong to turn the train in the standard trolley problem
setup. If even a significant minority of this group state the fat man should
be thrown off the bridge, it suggests that the fatness of the fat man is a
relevant factor in people's thinking about this issue.
In fact, as we can see from the chart to the right, only a very small
percentage of this group opt to sacrifice the fat man. Although the percentage
isn't zero, given that we would expect at least some inconsistency in
people's responses (consider, for example, that 20% of the same group opt
not to throw the fat man off the bridge in the circumstance where he's
responsible for damaging the train's brakes!), it is reasonable to conclude that for this subset of people at least,
the fatness of the fat man does not loom large in their decision making process.